-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 1
/
hypotheticals.rmd
1826 lines (1358 loc) · 160 KB
/
hypotheticals.rmd
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
# (PART) Theory {-}
# Pragmatic Hypotheticals {#hypotheticals}
<!-- % offe:
%write a 2nd order theory on the reform suggestion (such as offe 2009) -->
<!-- > There is a war between the rich and poor, a war between the man and the woman. -->
> There is a war between the ones who say there is a war and the ones who say there isn't.
>
> --- Leonard Cohen: New Skin for the Old Ceremony (1974)
> If they can get you asking the wrong questions, they don't have to worry about the answers.
>
> --- Thomas R. Pynchon (\*1937)
<!-- this works well for pragmatism:
> "Vain is the word of a philosopher which does not heal any suffering of man. For just as there is no profit in medicine if it does not expel the diseases of the body, so there is no profit in philosophy either, if it does not expel the suffering of the mind."
- Epicurus -->
<!-- %\begin{quote}
% \emph{``It is demonstrable'' said he,``that things cannot be otherwise than they are; for as all things have been created for some end, they must necessarily be created for the best end.
%%Observe, for instance, the nose is formed for spectacles; therefore we wear spectacles.
%The legs are visibly designed for stockings; accordingly we wear stockings.
%Stones were made to be hewn and to construct castles; therefore my lord has a magnificent castle; for the greatest baron in the province ought to be the best lodged.
%Swine were intended to be eaten; therefore we eat pork all year round.
%And they who assert that everything is right, do not express themselves correctly; they should say that everything is best.
% ''}\\*
% --- Dr.~Pangloss in Voltaire's novella \emph{Candide} (\citeyear{Voltaire1759}: K125).
%\end{quote} -->
To proceed by the method of elimination is always to conceive of such hypothetical outcomes, and then, to falsify them.
Still, hypotheticals
[^1]
are rarely invoked in social scientific explanations:
ever hear of an empirical sociologist or political scientist comparing the continental welfare state [@Esping-Andersen-1990-aa] or Westminster democracy [@Lijphart-1999-aa] to a *non-existent* alternative?
We can see why few empirical social scientists would ask such a question:
to say that taxation could be more efficient and equitable, and to suspect that someone (for example, the rich) or something (for example, capitalism) is preventing it from being so reeks off conspiracy theory.
Forensics, in some ways, has it easier:
if a coroner diagnoses heart failure from old age as the cause of death, there is no murder.
Just *which* social ills are unavoidable and thereby the social scientific equivalents to a natural death is, unfortunately, more contentious.
Plausibly, without the bullet, an otherwise healthy person might have lived to see another day, but writ on a societal level, such hypothesizing about alternative, preferable outcomes is hard.
Would democracy *not* always fall short of its ancient ideal, because we can no longer all meet and debate in person?
Would taxation *not* always be wasteful, because it suppresses otherwise pareto-improving exchanges?
Would welfare *not* always be a drag on growth, because it dampens incentives?
Empiricism
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:empiricism\]]{#itm:empiricism label="itm:empiricism"}
*"We cannot know"*, might reply the empiricist [@Bacon1620; @Locke1689; @Hume1739] because such hypotheticals can, by definition, not be experienced with our senses and nothing can be induced from them.
Whatever democracy, taxation and welfare *could be*, we cannot know.
Similarly, positivists might find these hypotheticals unknowable, either because absent, they *have been* falsified [@Comte1842; @Durkheim1895], or, because absent, they *cannot* be falsified [@Popper1934].
Idealism
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:idealism\]]{#itm:idealism label="itm:idealism"}
*"We know only through ideas"*, might respond the idealists [broadly @Kant1781; @Hegel1807], including the ideas invoked in these questions.
Whatever democracy, taxation and welfare *could be*, is beside the point, because our knowledge of them exists independent from their factual or hypothetical reality.
Specifically, interpretive sociologists [@Weber1897] might argue that the above questions may contain in them already one of several, cultural perspectives, ideas or terminologies in which all answers, too, would be have to be phrased.
"Waste", "growth" and 'incentives'' rather than objective things, already are cultural reality [compare @Beland2010].
Constructivism
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:constructivism\]]{#itm:constructivism label="itm:constructivism"}
*"Asks *who*?"*, might retort the constructivist [@Berger1966; @Paul1984], because these are not questions about an objectively knowable world, but rather, the act of asking these questions and of invoking these concepts *makes* that social world.
Whatever democracy, taxation and welfare *could be*, is beside the point, too, because legitimacy, efficiency, equity --- or any other criteria --- *become* real, as we think, demand and reject them.
Rationalism
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:rationalism\]]{#itm:rationalism label="itm:rationalism"}
*"We can know"*, might announce the rationalists [@Descartes1637; @Spinoza1662; @Leibniz1704] --- *"but hypothetical or actuality do not matter, either way"*.
Whatever democracy, taxation and welfare *could be*, we can know by deductive reasoning, without relying on our experience --- or absence thereof.
Clearly, *none* of these epistemologies taken to the extreme, can help investigate those desirable, and doable hypotheticals upon which I have stumbled.
Welfare, taxation and democracy certainly are ideas, but they are also bound by empirics.
They are accessible to deductive reasoning, but such reasoning can make a social world, as much as it seeks to explain it.
What I need, is a (p. ).
Equally clearly, such a cartoonish overview of epistemological traditions does not suffice to ground this dissertation.
Fortunately, this is --- as promised --- a pedestrian thesis and I will not abscond into any philosophy of science.
Unfortunately, I am also largely ignorant of these theories of knowledge, and can only provide a provisional epistemology that seems to work for democracy, taxation and welfare.
I take no pride in my epistemological ignorance, but I am weary of the obliviousness of these, and other meta-(meta?)-concerns.
In a slightly different context, Noam @Chomsky1997 has observed that "ontological questions are generally beside the point, hardly more than a form of harassment" [-@Chomsky1997 132].
As harassments go, I have found that such epistemological and ontological debates often arouse what would appear to be deeply-felt passions in even the drowsiest of graduate seminars.
This fervor always struck me as eerily performative [compare @Goffman1959; @Butler1997], as if, in addition to --- or as *part of*
[^2]
--- *doing gender* [@West1987], we were also *doing social science*.
If only to stick to my limited last, I prefer a social science that serves people other than its researchers, and accordingly sympathize with pragmatist epistemologies, where human problems are primary and reified "philosophical fallacies" [@Dewey1929] take a back seat to the problems they were invented to solve.
In @Wikipedia2013's apt description of an (ecologically) pragmatist epistemology:
"inquiry is how organisms can get a grip on their environment\" (retrieved in March 2013).
Even though, because hypotheticals are hardly invoked in the social sciences, are hard to specify, and are harder to know about I must devote this chapter to explicating the (p. ), (p. ) and (p. ) of my research.
## The Epistemology of Hypotheticals {#epistemology}
[^3]
Detective shows often confine the forensic medicine to some expository dialogue between coroner and inspector at the morgue.
I need a little more exposition here, stretching over several chapters of welfare economics, normative political theory and public choice, before the empirical action even begins.
Again, I merely proceed by the method of elimination.
To open an investigation, I must first know if there are alternative welfare states, taxes, and democracies out there, and if so, what they are.
Surely, to suggest that we might learn something about the world by asking what is *not* appears to be an odd epistemology.
Natural scientists probably do not spend much time thinking up, say, a counterfactual universe without gravity, and explaining why it is not (or maybe that *is* what they do at the Large Hadron Collider?!).
Positive social science, at least, needs to pose these why-not-questions, because, unlike physics, it is concerned with *who* or *what* made the world the way it *is*.
[^4]
Positive sociology, political science, and this dissertation, all ask such second-order questions.
Even to pose them, we need all the possible first-order answers of how the world *could* be, but is not.
The hypotheticals I establish in the following chapters are these first-order *non*-answers.
### First-Order Questions {#1st-questions}
Hypotheticals must be (p. ), and --- if you allow some humanist bias --- they must also be at least somewhat (p. ).
Those criteria both raise inquiries of the first order, asking what is normatively good and what is positively possible, respectively.
*Normative* (or prescriptive) social science asks such first-order questions as how to emancipate people (critical theory, maybe from @Gramsci1971 to @Adorno-1974-aa, Horkheimer and @Habermas-1984), what makes rule legitimate (political theory from @Aristoteles to @Dahl-1989-aa) or what allocation might be fair (distributive justice including @Friedman1962 and @Rawls1986) and even what makes an economy rich (economics from @Smith-1776-lq to @Hicks1939).
Even these apparently normative and first-order questions turn into positive and second-order questions when their underlying assumptions on human nature are tested or problematized, respectively (more on that twist on p. ).
*Positive* social science asks few, if any, first-order questions, because as it asks about the social world (for example, health insurance), it seeks to explain the social conflict of *answering* a first-order question (for example, how to spread risk).
To the extent that nominally *social* sciences have carved out positive research agendas of the first order (for example, cognitive psychology, behavioral economics), they cease to be social science but revert to a natural science of some ideally *physically* rooted phenomenon (for example, neuroscience).
Tautologically, if the social sciences are to be concerned with explaining social choice, they know *no* positive first-order questions, because first-order status negates choice.
[^5]
The aspects of the social world under study here are welfare, taxation and democracy.
To the extent that these social choices hinge on last reasons, they raise normative first-order questions.
These first-order questions of efficiency and equity, fairness and legitimacy have been widely discussed, and I will reference them only briefly in this dissertation.
But welfare, taxation and democracy also raise two kinds of positive questions:
[^6]
A Priori Knowledge
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:a-priori\]]{#itm:a-priori label="itm:a-priori"}
There may only be finite or even unique ways to organize these institutions that abide by *formal logic*, per reasoned, *a priori knowledge*.
For example, a welfare state financed solely by printing money may be an economically illogical institution (possibly resulting hyperinflation resembles a pyramid scheme).
Similarly, taxing judicial persons, such as corporations, may be economically nonsensical because such organizations are no moral subjects and the incidence would be arbitrary ().
As a last example, a democratic aggregation mechanism may not be able to maximize both majority rule and proportional representation, simply because the two criteria conflict.
Knowledge about what is logically possible or impossible flows from a epistemology (p. ).
A Posteriori Knowledge
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:a-posteriori\]]{#itm:a-posteriori label="itm:a-posteriori"}
These formally logical designs may be further limited by empirical, first-order findings on human nature or other material conditions, per experiential, *a posteriori* knowledge.
For example, a welfare state financed by extracting and burning fossil fuels may soon run into physical constraints if we observe limited resources and related global warming.
Similarly, a fully-planned economy (instead of taxation) may, amongst other things, dramatically overestimate the cognitive ability of human planners to centrally aggregate and process dispersed information.
Lastly, a democracy modeled on ancient Athens, but with universal suffrage and in globally integrated economies may fail simply because human beings interact too slowly to listen to every fellow human on the planet, let alone to get anything done.
[^7]
Knowledge about what is empirically possible or impossible flows from an epistemology (p. ).
These are, admittedly, uncontroversial constraints and ludicrous suggestions --- I want to keep the more interesting problems for later --- but they illustrate an important point:
there probably *are* some first-order, positive limits the social world faces, even though we may know little and disagree a lot about them.
Crucially, we may disagree on whether a given question is of the first or second order.
The social sciences, in particular, have a habit of reassigning first-order questions to second-order status:
*that* is the project of constructivism [for example, @Berger1966] and (p. ) to see social phenomena not as "things *in* the world, but perspectives *on* the world" [@Brubaker-2002-aa 174 on ethnicity, emphasis in the original] or as contested and consequential second-order *answers*.
<!-- also the project of poststructuralism -->
Still, even a die-hard idealist or constructivist may concede some irreducibly positive, first-order questions, and to those, the social sciences offer no answers.
So it is with welfare, taxation and democracy.
Their design probably faces some --- albeit uncertain and contested --- positive limits of the first order.
To ask about these limits is, emphatically, *not* a question for the social sciences.
Instead, *nominally* social scientific, but formally mathematical-logical disciplines such as equilibrium economics
[^8]
and public choice ask about the internal consistency
of such societal institutions, based on assumptions on (p. ), which are in turn hypothesized and falsified by such natural sciences as evolutionary psychology (a.k.a. sociobiology), social psychology [initially @KahnemanTversky1979], cognitive science, or even physics.
I suggest two examples of such first-order, positive substrates relevant to my subject matter:
1. The first theorem of welfare economics is often invoked as a first-order constraint on welfare state interventions or taxation (the [dwl]{acronym-label="dwl" acronym-form="singular+short"}), and it also shines through in some radical defenses of pluralist democracy [for example, @Caplan2007].
The theorem states that over any *given* distribution, free competition equilibrates at pareto optimality
[^9]
and that therefore, no allocative intervention can make anyone better off without making someone else worse off.
It is a mathematically formulated argument about some internal consistency of the market mechanism:
given certain (p. ), market equilibria *cannot* be pareto-improved.
As such, the theorem is just that, an exercise in formal logic, not more:
not empirical claim (no "proof" that *actual* markets pareto-optimize) and not normative statement (no justification for pareto-optimization over existing distributions as desirable).
But the first theorem is also not less:
properly understood, it *is* a first-order constraint and invites *no* second-order critique.
2. Similarly, homo economicus is often invoked in the field of welfare (*"knaves"* as in @LeGrand2003), taxation (*"people react to incentives"* as in @Mankiw-2004-aa [24]) and democracy (*"rationally irrational"* as in @Caplan2007).
The concept implies that human beings make rational, self-interested and utility-maximizing decisions (maybe first @Mill1848, @Smith-1776-lq, recently including @Robbins1976 on rational choice, all summarized in @Persky1995).
The ideological campaign (and backlash) wrought by homo economicus and its offspring notwithstanding, it is, properly understood, merely a *falsifiable*
[^10]
assumption about human nature that welfare, taxation and democracy might have to heed if it were, in fact, correct.
But even if it were true, homo economicus would be just that, an empirically verified model:
no more (no normative claim of how we *should* be), but also no less (no socially contingent phenomenon in need of deconstruction).
### Second-Order Questions {#2nd-questions}
As forensics informs a criminal investigation, the first-order answers provide the reference for the second order inquiries.
These ask who or what decides first-order answers, or, metaphorically, who or what brought about the observed forensic outcome (see , p. ).
Second-order inquiries seek to criticize, explain or test the *social conflict* over first-order questions.
Social science asks plenty of those questions on welfare, taxation and democracy.
It asks, for example, why and how welfare states --- a first-order *answer* --- evolve(d):
because modernization replaced inherited, familial status with citizenship and the market [@Titmuss1974; @Marshall-1950-aa], because industrialization required an appeased, reliable and healthy workforce [@Flora1981; @Wilensky1975], because workers gained power [@Korpi1983; @Jessop2002], because institutions prevail [for example, @Rothstein], because ideas matter [for example, @Stiller2009] because initial class cleavages lead to different degrees of commodification [@Esping-Andersen-1990-aa] or because capitalism comes in variants [@HallSoskice-2001-aa].
[^11]
So it is with the second-order theories of taxation:
it arose as proto-states extracted the resources enabled by, and necessary for greater economies of scale in their state-making and war-making [@Tilly-1985-aa], it (sometimes) erodes to lower levels as internationally mobile factors of production and consumption arbitrage over different national rates (recently reviewed in @Genschel2010), it persists at similar levels as domestic politics prevents roll-back [@Swank2002], or it changes bases and schedule in response to these pressures [@Kemmerling2009].
<!-- %need more general literature here, not this contentious one-sided stuff, maybe more from the fiscal sociology stuff. -->
And so, too, it is with the second-order theory of pluralist democracy:
states introduced popular rule, because the costs of otherwise considered illegitimate extraction became prohibitive [@Tilly2006], democracy belongs to a broader syndrome of emancipating modernization, including a market economy and corresponding rational and self-expression values [@InglehartWelzel-2005-aa] or the sequential development of citizenship (instead of other, pre-modern statuses) entailed democratic rights [@Marshall-1950-aa].
<!-- %need more general literature here -->
These are variations on the questions of sociology:
what binds us together (social integration), and what keeps us apart (social inequality).
[^12]
These are also the questions of political science:
how do power, norms, ideas and institutions rule human interactions?
These second-order questions are open to all epistemologies, including the the anti-positivist traditions of and .
They can also be --- as seems to be currently en vogue
[^13]
---, *but need not be*, entirely or, inquiries.
And important questions, they are, asking us, that lone "hypercultural" species [@Henrich2004], how we make our own history.
In our rich time and in our unequal place, welfare, taxation and democracy may just be *the* historical battlegrounds, on which these sociological and political forces operate.
This dissertation develops a second-order theory of social change to explain the defeats these institutions have suffered in late capitalism, and tests it empirically.
[^14]
\centering
![image](orders-of-questions){width="1\linewidth"}
The distinction between first-, second-order, normative and positive questions summarized in (p. ) matters for at least two reasons:
1. Clearly addressing one of these questions at a time, and striving to keep them separate makes for better social science.
With these categorically different questions come different goals, languages and methods.
With blurring or negating these categories come "politics-based evidence making" (The Economist 2012), apolitical ignorance or both.
2. Because positive social science --- including this dissertation --- is out to explain the second-order decision on first-order questions, it must consider some first-order theory *first*.
### First Order Theory *First* {#1st-questions-first}
I am ultimately interested in the second-order questions of welfare, taxation and democracy, but proceeding by the method of elimination, I must first ask and answer the first-order questions:
what *should* and *could* welfare, taxation and democracy look like.
Consider the two alternatives, that I must rule out before any second-order questions can be raised:
No Desirable Hypothetical.
: If I could find only the presently observed design of welfare, tax and democracy to be at least somewhat desirable, there would be no social conflict to be explained, much like there is no need for a political science of wearing sunscreen.
(I partly take this , p. ).
In the crime story metaphor, if the corpse in question had previously run amok shooting innocents, rupturing that persons coronary artery with a bullet might be have been self-defense or the last resort, and the only desirable course of action.
No *further* criminal investigation may be necessary.
No Doable Hypothetical.
: If I could find only the presently observed design of tax and democracy to be materially doable, there would be no social conflict to be explained, much like there is no need for a sociological theory of gravity.
In the crime story metaphor, if said deceased suffered from an irreparable birth defect that caused the heart failure, no outcome but death is materially possible.
In that case, too, no criminal investigation will be necessary.
<!-- %add table here to further explain these.
%crosstab it. -->
Conceiving such to-be-ruled-out hypotheticals raises normative (desirability) and positive (doability) questions of the *first*-order.
These first-order questions cannot, as I explained above, be answered by social sciences (alone), but I must instead reference other disciplines, much like a detective hears forensic evidence.
If these ancillary disciplines reveal one, or several such desirable and doable hypotheticals that I cannot rule out, the non-occurrence of such hypothetical welfare, taxation and democracy beg a second-order explanation just as the observed arrangement requires explanation.
In fact, the two are the same thing:
to explain the presence of the present arrangement is to explain the absence of all absent arrangements.
For illustration, consider the inverse scenario, in which I find no desirable and doable hypotheticals in welfare, taxation and democracy.
If that were the case, there would be no second-order decision to be explained, because without such hypotheticals, there is no human choice.
If however, there *are* desirable and doable hypotheticals, any second-order question always invokes these hypotheticals.
### Fallacies and Risks
<!-- %better title:
%glass full empty? -->
To be sure, this reasoning is not logically watertight and might turn into an argument from ignorance:
even if I find no reason why hypotheticals should, or could not be, they might still be undesirable or impossible for some other reason.
Absence of evidence, here, too, does not constitute evidence of absence.
The same problem must plague medical forensics:
no evidence of natural death does not prove a violent death and any conclusion to the contrary might cause an unnecessary murder investigation.
In practice, this possible fallacy simply raises the question of where you place the burden of proof, because you can err either way:
if you take absence of evidence of violent death as evidence of natural death, you might foreclose a necessary investigation and let someone get away with murder.
Tellingly, when it comes to human corpses we place the burden of proof on the status quo:
if the cause of death cannot be established --- if there is *no* evidence of natural death --- the prosecution customarily opens an investigation.
<!-- %find source for this -->
The positive social science of welfare, tax and democracy seems to have adopted a somewhat laxer standard.
Here, much empirical work implicitly places the burden of proof on the hypothetical:
without evidence that the hypothetical is normatively desirable and materially possible, the fundamental status quo of welfare and tax needs no social explanation.
Conveniently, as hypotheticals go, they rarely produce conclusive evidence of their desirability and doability.
Maybe, this is just the skepticism that positivism calls for --- or maybe, , and such social science invariable turns latently affirmative (, p. ).
Either way, I here place the burden of proof on the status quo.
If I find no reasons to the contrary, I assume that there *are* several doable and desirable designs of tax and democracy, and require social science to explain the *absence* of all but the presently observed design.
If we apply the standard of forensics, any second-order theory of social change must be able to explain how the social conflict under study resulted in the non-occurrence of these alternative designs, especially the attractive ones.
I still want to shoulder part of the burden of proof.
In tax, I can only plausibilize the hypotheticals by reviewing reputable work by others, and deduce my case from reasonable assumptions about human nature, and the economy.
I must rely mostly on a epistemology (p. ).
Natural experiments --- the gold standard --- are unavailable, and all others suffer from limited external validity:
a modern economy does not fit in the laboratory and equilibrium simulations poorly model such inframarginal institutional changes.
<!-- %more on this somewhere else.
%Should explain why I can't look into tax in another way! Reference this section here. -->
In democracy, I similarly plausibilize the hypotheticals, but I can also point to and undertake some preliminary experimental tests.
To suggest, as I do, that there are desirable and doable hypotheticals in tax and democracy, must remain a preliminary proposition open to falsification.
To the @Popper1934ian scientist, there is always some absence of evidence, and therefore, no evidence of absence.
If these particular hypotheticals turn out to be undesirable or impossible, so collapses any second-order hypothesis I might wager later, but, I hope, we will still have learned something.
Not only the advancement of science depends on such falsification, the history of progressive causes is also littered with what might charitably be called "false positives".
My chosen hypotheticals --- deliberative democracy and progressive taxation of (unimproved) land value and (postpaid) consumption, too, may inspire such false hopes.
They, too, should be approached with great care, especially, when they necessitate constitutional or otherwise reform of liberal democracy, as deliberative democracy may one day do.
Tax reform, at least, should be open to falsification and is not an end in itself, especially because it thoroughly hinges on economic contexts and human motivation.
Then again, by any historical standard --- once-hypotheticals failed (for example, socialism) and successful (for example, universal suffrage) alike --- here are some fairly incremental reforms as carefully liberal in their (p. ) as they are conservative about (p. ).
## Axioms for Desirable Hypotheticals {#axiology}
<!-- %or last reasons? -->
> *"I believe in clear-cut positions.
> I think that the most arrogant position is this apparent, multidisciplinary modesty of *'what I am saying now is not unconditional, it is just a hypothesis,'* and so on.
> \[...\]
> I think that the only way to be honest and expose yourself to criticism is to state clearly and dogmatically where you are.
> You must take the risk and have a position."*\
> --- Slavov @Zizek2003 [45]
Normatively desirable hypotheticals are preferable to others if we assume a basic humanist, or critical intention of positive social science and policy analysis to improve human lives.
From a strictly positivist point of view, this is the flimsiest of epistemological decisions I take:
we might learn just as much about the social world from the nonoccurrence of bad outcomes, as from the nonoccurence of good outcomes.
[^15]
My bias for desirable hypotheticals might be epistemologically arbitrary, but it is --- again --- pragmatic:
there may just be so many undesirable, but doable counterfactuals (why *not* return to workhouses rather than welfare, tariffs rather than taxation and mob rule rather than liberal democracy?) that it becomes plainly easier to pick amongst the supposedly fewer, attractive hypotheticals.
Moreover --- if mostly implicitly --- modernization theory, (structural) functionalism and related traditions might have convincingly explained away some of those graver regresses of civilization.
Lastly --- only slightly tongue-in-cheek ---, on a second look at the factual horror chamber of welfare, tax and democracy, there might not be *that* many even less desirable, doable hypotheticals left.
What then, makes for desirable hypotheticals?
Emphatically, hypothetical tax, welfare and democracy, and with them, this research, hinge on last reasons.
Desirable tax and welfare are rational, efficient and fair.
Democracy, too, must be these things and more:
emancipatory, equal and deliberative.
Unfortunately, these last reasons sometimes conflict, and they do not even flow from any single ethic.
What makes my hypothetical tax, welfare and democracy desirable is, instead, a hodgepodge of mongrels from quite distinct normative theories.
I here list five of them and show how they apply to taxation, welfare and democracy:
Virtue Ethics [\[itm:virtue\]]{#itm:virtue label="itm:virtue"}
: Tax, welfare and democracy are not desirably merely to the extent that they constitute, or foster *virtue* inherent to human action and character (from @Aristotelesa, @Plato, @St.ThomasAcquinas1274 to @schwartz2006practical).
At least under neoclassical dictum, tax and welfare are desirable to the extent that they *do not* depend on, nor improve human virtue, but efficiently orchestrate our selfish demons [compare @Smith-1776-lq].
Liberal democracy, similarly, is desirable to the extent that it sidesteps questions of personal virtue and guarantees an agnostic process for all people, no matter the quality of their character [compare @Dahl-1989-aa].
And yet, I rely on virtue ethics when I praise markets and states for letting us reap (p. ), that supposed destiny of our nature [for example, @Wright2000].
The case for deliberative democracy, too --- as all virtue ethics --- implies a *telos* of human life, to the extent that it posits intersubjective understanding or *communicative action* as a last reason [@Habermas-1984].
Consequentialism [\[itm:consequentialism\]]{#itm:consequentialism label="itm:consequentialism"}
: Tax, welfare and democracy are also not desirable merely by the outcomes they produce, be they utility [@Bentham1789; @Mill1863] or even self-interest [@Rand1957].
Attractive consequences, especially different aggregate functions of utility
[^16]
go a long way to justifying taxation and welfare, but I would not bet the farm on them.
Even if, say, relative inequality were empirically unrelated to "subjective happiness" (as @KalmijnVeenhoven-2005-aa seem to imply),
<!-- %check this reference -->
and progressive taxation therefore not a maximizer of aggregate happiness, at least two other reasons would remain:
1. Straightforwardly, we might wish to maximize consequences *other* than some measure of hedonistic gain, including equality, growth, knowledge or liberty.
Utilitarianism --- as other consequentialisms --- side-step entirely the question of how the desired consequences would be measured, and who would do the observing.
[^17]
Utilitarianism merely posits an *ideal observer* [@Rawls1988] --- such as @Veenhoven-2000-aa's subjective happiness --- and does not allow us to problematize the conditions under which consequences are enumerated, or measured.
[^18]
2. More fundamentally, progressive taxation --- or some other policy --- may remain attractive not because of *any* distribution or measurement of consequence, but because equality might be inherently *virtuous*, or the goods it can buy (including universal health care) may be a matter of *deontological* rights.
The consequentialist case for democracy is even thinner:
as @Dahl-1989-aa [176] reminds us, equal intrinsic worth of humans *alone* might be achieved by a benevolent dictator.
Only in conjunction with (deontological? virtuous?) personal autonomy does it require democratic rule.
And yet, hypotheticals about taxation and welfare, and even democracy cannot ignore consequences, especially (p. ) and its (p. ).
Deontological Ethics
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:deontological\]]{#itm:deontological label="itm:deontological"}
Tax, welfare and democracy are also not merely desirable to the extend that they abide by some set of absolute rights and duties.
On the one hand, most such deontological ethics are not specific enough to inform choices of tax, welfare and democracy.
For instance, the Golden Rule --- *do unto others as you would have done to yourself* --- may not tell us much about what we should tax, when we should intervene in the market or how we should count votes.
@Kant1781's similar categorical imperative is equally mum on these matters, maybe because his is a philosophy and
deals with *man* in the singular, not *men* in the plural as @Arendt1958 demanded of political theory.
[^19]
Natural rights theories (from @Grotius1625), be they liberal (from @Locke1689a to maybe @Rawls-1993-aa), spinoff (right-)libertarian (diverse, prominently @Hayek1944, @Nozick1974) concerned with negative freedoms *from* (for example, false imprisonment), or positive freedoms *to* (for example, human dignity, both @Berlin1969) provide more guidelines, but they, too, are limited.
Natural rights theories, and especially liberalism, set outer limits on what a government or person must not do *to*, or must not fail to do *for* the bearers of these rights, but they are too digital for a normative ethic of welfare, taxation and democracy.
For example, market interventions may be either permissible (freedom-to) or illegitimate (right-libertarianism), but natural rights do not offer much qualifications in-between.
It is of course the great appeal of natural rights that they are unconditional (as in *"Human dignity shall be inviolable"*, German Basic Law 1948) and pre-social (as in *"...that all men are created equal"*, US Declaration of Independence 1776), but that makes them a little too lofty for inherently social, and contingent institutions as welfare and taxation.
There may, for example, be many (or no) taxes that allow for *life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness* (*ibid.*), but it would be a stretch to argue that these natural rights are best respected or least harmed by any particular tax on consumption, income or wealth.
Crucially, too, many collective decisions in late capitalism must balance one persons liberty, against another persons pursuit of happiness, or similar rival natural rights.
Contract theories (from @Hobbes-1651-aa, @Rousseau1762 to @Rawls-1971) are more specific still, by prescribing a decision-making process or condition to balance and protect rival rights.
While this may suffice to specify a desirable democracy (authoritatively @Dahl-1989-aa on *liberal*, *pluralist* poliarchy), contract theories still recede into procedural norms on taxation and welfare.
@Dahl-1989-aa --- but not @Rawls-1971, as we shall see! --- may inform us about how we should decide between, say, an income or a consumption tax, but abstains from substantive judgement.
When, however, the very quality of the (second-order) decision process over these tax choices is in question --- as it is in this dissertation --- evaluating first-order hypotheticals by a procedural standard risks infinite regress:
a tax is good if the process was good, and the process is good if the tax is good, which is good if ...and so on.
<!-- %consider including the visualization about euler diagrams and production possibility frontiers in here? -->
On the other hand, tax and welfare especially, are institutions that negotiate and trade off competing rights and duties, rather than strictly abide by them.
Natural rights to, say, property *and* health care, offer no all-or-nothing propositions in taxation.
Instead, one tax may encroach *less* on property than another, or at a greater (utilitarian) gain in health care than another.
In sum, deontological ethics, and especially its popular, liberal, contractual and procedural representatives are both not specific enough, and too demanding for desirable hypotheticals in welfare, taxation and democracy.
And yet, I cannot do without deontological ethics, especially not without liberalism.
Even if governments *could* expropriate some owners at supposedly minimal welfare losses --- as the Eurogroup has allowed (encouraged?) the Cypriot government to proceed in 2013 with big savers --- it should not do so (nor be allowed to), because protection of confidence is a deontological right.
Similarly, even if democratic rule found executive pay excessive, and anticipated no [dwl]{acronym-label="dwl" acronym-form="singular+short"} fallout, it should not --- as Switzerland did in 2013 --- regulate *uncoerced exchanges* [@Nozick1974] even between CEOs and shareholders, when a less intrusive policy (tax!) is available, simply because liberal states do not do that.
<!-- %find better, thesis-related examples -->
Ethics of Care
: [\[itm:ethics-of-care\]]{#itm:ethics-of-care label="itm:ethics-of-care"}
Lastly, tax, welfare and democracy are, for the most part, *not* desirable because they establish caring relationships, as some (difference?) feminists have demanded [@Noddings1984; @Gilligan1982].
Whether we like it or not --- in fact, we *should* like it --- our world is ruled by abstractions, too, and to these must respond our institutions of tax, welfare and democracy.
Absent a regress to lower, poorer levels of functional differentiation --- or some yet unforeseen explosion in human capacity --- we depend on wide-ranging abstractions such as a price system to orchestrate at least some of our relationships by mutual self-interest.
[^20]
Ethics of care govern *individual*, *concrete* and *personal* relationships, and not those anonymously expressed in price signals, or some other abstraction.
Taxation, welfare and democracy, however, *have* to ontologically respond to such abstractions, and to that extent, cannot be informed by a normative ethic that insists otherwise.
And yet, I cannot abandon an ethic of care entirely.
For once, *caring* reminds me that we may have other, more intimately personal capacities (or duties?) for goodness and desirable taxation, welfare and democracy may consequently have to leave room for caring to flourish.
For example, I imply an ethic of care when I later suggest that taxation should respect the promises of (mutual) care in marriage and family and not discourage, nor commodify such unions.
More broadly, a good welfare system might have to carve out realms where such necessarily *priceless* care can be extended --- not *exchanged*! --- and might have to reallocate resources to those, especially women, who spend much of their energy caring for others, without compensation.
Something akin to ethics of care are also implied by some proponents of deliberative democracy, maybe including those who stress the importance of story-telling in democratic participation [@Poletta2006].
Deliberative formats may also raise ethical questions of care simply because they make people engage with other people.
Intersubjective understanding certainly requires the kind of personal relationships to which ethics of care supposedly apply.
I know then, that I know nothing --- at least nothing consistent --- about what makes tax, welfare and democracy desirable.
That might be a socratic moment, but not a happy one for me or this dissertation.
It frustrates me that I can summarize these ethics only in the crudest of terms, and that I fail to synthesize them.
Such ignorance is troubling, too, for research as this, based on a social science education as devoid of normative theory as mine:
clearly, these theories matter for tax, welfare and democracy as for any scholarship about them.
Tracking down the choices and controversies in tax, welfare and democracy to different ethics is important work that I have to do without, resting this work on quite murky foundations.
All I can offer is a modicum of argumentative transparency, by labeling any downstream axioms in tax, welfare and democracy with the roughly appropriate normative ethics from which they flow.
Because none of the above ethics are sufficient, but each of them necessary to formulate desirable tax, welfare and democracy, I subscribe neither to virtue, nor consequentialist, nor deontological, nor care ethics but pick and choose amongst them.
I guess that makes me an ethical pragmatist of sorts, if a confused one.
Pragmatic Ethics
<!-- %for all the pragmatism, check \cite{Bohman1999} -->
: [\[itm:pragmatic-ethics\]]{#itm:pragmatic-ethics label="itm:pragmatic-ethics"}
--- not identical with pragmatism, and never to be confused with realism or *Realpolitik* --- may best enumerate what makes tax, welfare and democracy desirable, for at least two reasons:
1. In pragmatic ethics, morality can progress over time [@Dewey1932], much as science advances through iterative inquiry.
Such tentative morality implies neither relativism, nor inaction:
there may still be absolute values out there, we just cannot be sure that we have distilled them yet, but should act on whichever approximation we have tentatively arrived at.
Tax, welfare and democracy, too, are such inherently tentative and contingent enterprises.
For example, when comprehensive income taxes were introduced to more neatly bifurcated class societies, the ethical quandaries of taxing labor and capital incomes might not have been foreseeable:
labor income generally accrued to poor workers, capital incomes to rich capitalists, end of story.
Similarly, as universal suffrage was wrung from the *ancien regimes* and liberal democracy enshrined to fend off mob rule around the same time, the limits of a merely electoral and pluralist democracy in a complex world might not have been conceivable.
So too, no doubt, will the reforms of tax, welfare and democracy I suggest here reveal their blind spots, come progress.
Acknowledging that our moral understanding may be imperfect, or even somewhat historically contingent, also in no way restricts us to the status quo under which this understanding was reached.
Pragmatic ethics can be quite radical, maybe *because* it accepts its own tentativeness and contingence:
we can "transform the character of our relation to social and cultural worlds we inhabit rather than just to change, little by little, the content of the arrangements and beliefs that comprise them." [@Unger2007 6-7].
I am inspired by such *anti-necessitarianism* [@Unger1987], even if --- or because? --- tax, welfare and democracy are not the stuff of revolution, but rather the "indispensable if insufficient \[...\] piecemeal and cumulative change in the organization of society" [@Unger1987 xix].
I am keenly aware that especially reformed tax and welfare, but even deliberative democracy will, at best, progress us a little further to a point where we --- probably our progeny --- can better conceive morality, and undertake further tentative transformations we cannot even dream of.
2. Pragmatic ethics are also, as the name implies, intensely practical.
Pragmatic ethics cannot be conceived of in other than practical terms:
> *"Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have.
> Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object."*\
<!-- %add first name, correct? -->
> --- William @Peirce1878 [293]
This *pragmatic maxim*, as it became later known, works well, especially for tax and welfare.
The proverbial proof of their ethical pudding, too, lies in the eating.
For example, a tax on income or consumption becomes good or bad greatly by how it works in practice:
what it curtails, what it wastes or what it hurts --- very little of which can be read in the Platonic idea of either of those alone.
Admittedly, such pragmatic ethics are fairly amorphous, and they do not constitute any of the clear-cut positions that @Zizek2003 demand in the above.
They merely provide the normative theory under which I can organize, and justify the following hodgepodge of axioms for desirable hypotheticals in tax, welfare and democracy.
Here then, are my positions.
### Liberal Limits and Procedure {#liberal}
Desirable hypotheticals in tax, welfare and democracy are liberal.
They do not infringe on the most extensive basic liberties compatible with similar liberty for others [@Rawls-1971], a liberal formulation of the *Golden Rule* of reciprocity.
These include the political and civil liberties enshrined in various liberal constitutions, but, following @Rawls-1971 *do not* extend to unencumbered private property of the means of production or unlimited freedom of contract, as libertarians would have it.
Desirable hypotheticals in tax, welfare and democracy must be liberal both in the substance of, as well as in the process by which they bring about social chance.
Substantively, these regimes must not constrain the lifestyles of people, except if and to the extent that such choices conflict with --- as @Rawls-1971 posited --- the choices others.
This is, for example, a very real concern in making consumption taxes progressive, or in taxing savings, both without dictating consumption baskets or prescribing a financial biography.
Similarly, democratic fora should encourage "*alternative* conceptions of the common good" [@Cohen-1989-aa 18, emphasis added] rather than promote a specific social change, even if such a coherent scientific agenda *could* be found.
This insistence on a plurality of lifestyles and ideas of the good distinguish a desirable hypothetical from totalitarian zeal and hermetic ideology.
Procedurally, desirable hypotheticals rely on democratic advocacy, not armchair guardianship to become real.
No matter, say, the (p. ) value of a [pct]{acronym-label="pct" acronym-form="singular+short"}, its introduction must respect, as @Dahl-1989-aa has highlighted, *both* (!) intrinsic equality [-@Dahl-1989-aa 84] *and* (liberal!) personal autonomy [-@Dahl-1989-aa 97ff].
In his influential formulation [@Dahl-1989-aa 109ff.], it can only be realized by a democratic process marked by at least:
1. effective participation,
2. voting equality at the decisive state,
3. enlightened understanding and,
4. control of the agenda and
5. inclusiveness
<!-- not sure about this last one %Equality must extend to all citizens within the state.
%Everyone has legitimate stake within the political process.[citation needed] -->
These criteria imply a fairly conventional catalogue of *negative* rights, or freedoms *from* and a standard formulation of democratic process (but not substance).
Together, these liberal norms take precedence over any of the other, below axioms for desirable hypotheticals:
in @Rawls-1971's formulation for his *Theory of Justice*, violations of any of these rights "cannot be justified or remedied by other \[...\] advantages" [-@Rawls-1971 81].
They cannot be traded off other benefits, but can only be limited when they come in conflict with one another, as for example, freedom of speech and defamation legislation may.
<!-- %might refer to later section on justice
%reference, include visualization? -->
I posit these rights (), but I also think (p. ) that for the foreseeable future, these norms may be our best, if tentative and minimal bet of what people and government should *never* do to people.
Maybe, liberal and other deontological norms can also serve under some kind of precautionary principle in ethics:
given at least some uncertainty over, or contradiction within other normative ethics --- especially consequentialism --- we should accept liberal limits to policy because they might help reduce some assymetric downside risks.
### Rational Preferences {#rational}
Desirable hypotheticals in tax, welfare and democracy are based on and help people express rationally coherent preferences.
[@VonNeumannMorgenstern1944] have axiomatized rational coherence thus:
Completeness
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:completeness\]]{#itm:completeness label="itm:completeness"}
For any two alternatives, $A$ and $B$, we either ordinally prefer $A$ to $B$, or $B$ to $A$ or are indifferent between $A$ and $B$.
Transitivity
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:transitivity\]]{#itm:transitivity label="itm:transitivity"}
For every three alternatives $A$, $B$ and $C$, where we prefer $A$ over $B$ and $B$ over $C$, we must prefer $A$ over $C$.
Continuity
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:continuity\]]{#itm:continuity label="itm:continuity"}
For every three alternatives $A$, $B$ and $C$, where we prefer $A$ over $B$ over $C$, there is a lottery comprised of a known number of $A$-lots and $C$-lots between which and $B$ we are indifferent.
And, most controversially,
Independence
: \phantomsection
[\[itm:independence\]]{#itm:independence label="itm:independence"}
If between two alternatives $A$ and $B$, we prefer $A$, given a third option, $X$, we still prefer $A$ over $B$.
Such [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rational actors can be said to have *well-formed*, *ordinal* preferences over given alternatives, and can, by @VonNeumannMorgenstern1944's work, express equivalent, unique and *cardinal* preferences over these alternatives.
That is, if an actor can *rank* alternatives [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rationally, she can also assign them a set of equivalent real numbers, such as willingness to pay.
@VonNeumannMorgenstern1944's transformation of ordinal preferences into cardinal utility can be roughly imagined thus:
[^21]
An agent is offered many lotteries with known probabilities of the alternative outcomes in question.
If the agent is [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rational, her ordinal preferences dictate her choice between *any* such known probabilities revealing her *expected* utility function, including those probabilities where she is indifferent between alternatives.
Probabilities being cardinal, the agent's choices between them reveal her cardinal utility from the alternatives.
A [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rational agent's ordinal preferences can thereby always be expressed in some cardinal utility function, and vice versa:
if an agent has a cardinal utility function over ordinally preferred alternatives, she must be [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rational.
Crucially, cardinal *utility* thus revealed need not be a linear function of some cardinal *value*:
agents *expected utility* may differ from the *expected value* of some outcome, where its value is merely multiplied by its probability.
Agents, can, for example be risk averse and display a correspondingly concave utility function.
[^22]
In the social sciences, expected utility theory --- as its brethren the first theorem of welfare economics --- often arouses great passions:
it is either considered elegant and self-evident, or vulgar and misleading.
Here too, I must briefly explicate its status:
1. Expected utility theory is knowledge (p. ) of the first-order flowing from a epistemology (p. ).
It implies no (first-order, empirical) observations of actual human decision making.
<!-- %, nor does it suggest any (second-order, normative) prescriptions of how people should decide. -->
[^23]
As other exercises in formal logic, it is not up to social scientific debate.
2. Expected utility theory invites *no* intersubjective comparisons (such as those on which the first theorem of welfare economics rest).
Any talk of *aggregate* expected utility is meaningless, absent additional assumptions.
That said, expected utility theory can provide no justification for any particular aggregation or comparison of individual utility, but once such aggregation has been accomplished on other grounds (for example, by democratic rule), it can posit rationality for and guide decisions based on such aggregated preferences.
Why now, readers may ask, does any of this matter?
Expected utility theory matters a great deal for desirable hypotheticals in tax, welfare and democracy.
In tax and welfare it suggests the very necessary and sufficient (!) conditions under which it even makes sense to speak of utility, or its manifold incarnations in (cardinal!) economics.
Markets can work their hypothesized magic of pareto-optimization under the first theorem of welfare economics if, and only if people can express their preferences [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rationally.
If people displayed, say, preferences between good $A$ and $B$ depended on a luxury good $C$ becoming available in a market [@Frank2010a], the whole intellectual artifice of "utility" and any pursuant neoliberal imperatives with it, may crumble.
Tax and welfare may have to step in, to rectify the original irrationality.
Conversely, to justify any of my desired welfare interventions into the market economy is to argue for enhanced expected utility:
assuming (reasonably, I think), that people prefer an $A$ of no insurance premium, livelong health, to a $B$ of some insurance premium, cared-for sickness, to a $C$ of some insurance premium, livelong health, to a $D$ of no insurance premium, uncared-for sickness, but suggesting that, when they give the probabilities and their risk aversion some thought, people (should) find $B$ to be of maximal expected utility, is to invoke @VonNeumannMorgenstern1944.
The case is even clearer in democracy.
On the one hand, [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rationality specifies what can be accepted as ordinal preference inputs (votes), if their bearers (citizens) are to have some consistent expected utility in the face of risky choice (strategic voting!).
On the other hand, these [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"} axioms must also be accepted by any democratic aggregation mechanism --- even if, absent meaningful intersubjective comparisons, @VonNeumannMorgenstern1944 cannot justify any particular mode of aggregation.
As I hypothesize later, popular tax choice under pluralism may well be plagued by irrational, inconsistent preferences of voters, and suboptimal choice in tax may, in part, be attributed to an aggregation mode that exploits these flawed preferences.
<!-- %add reference -->
Conversely, it appears that even assuming [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-rational voters, aggregative democracy alone may not be able to produce minimally attractive decisions.
<!-- %add references -->
Expected utility theory not only serves me to elucidate such *a priori* consequences, my normative conviction goes further and deeper.
To speak of rationally maximizing utility, as I wish to do, *is* to imply @VonNeumannMorgenstern1944, at least for now.
Without their axioms for rationality, we do not know what we are talking about when we say "utility", and conversely, without their formulation of utility, we do not know what we are talking about when we say "rationality".
If the two are to mean anything, I suspect, they must be related in the terms that @VonNeumannMorgenstern1944 have worked out.
### Pragmatic Utilitarianism {#utilitarian}
<!-- %this title also doesn't work well. -->
Desirable hypotheticals in tax, welfare and democracy maximize outcomes that are valuable to people.
Unfortunately, such a utilitarian axiom raises more questions than
it answers, including:
1. [\[itm:aggregation\]]{#itm:aggregation label="itm:aggregation"}
How do we aggregate value over different people?
2. [\[itm:utility\]]{#itm:utility label="itm:utility"}
How can we know what people value?
I cannot explore these questions in full, let alone answer them.
Yet, to suggest desirable tax, welfare and democracy *without* raising these questions would be charlatanry.
Without at least a tentative and pragmatic response to these questions, there can be no meaningful talk about their (p. ).
Question [\[itm:aggregation\]](#itm:aggregation){reference-type="ref" reference="itm:aggregation"} is easier to dismiss (if not answer), so I will deal with it first.
#### The Problem of Aggregation {#aggregation}
Utilitarianism runs into an empirical, or even ontological problem when it comes to aggregating value over different people:
it posits an ideal observer capable of comparing value between people.
[^24]
Sadly (or not?) such an ideal observer is not readily available [@Rawls1988], and we do not even know whether such intersubjective comparison is ontologically possible.
This is not to say that absent an *ideal* observer, we are off the hook.
We *should* care about other people with whatever roundabout empathy we can muster, but, strictly speaking, we should *not* do it for utilitarian reasons.
The last reasons for which we should care about the consequences of others are precisely not consequentialist, but may be, for instance, deontological (equality!), virtuous (charity!) or caring (empathy!).
Utilitarianism *cannot*, as [@Bentham1789] might have hoped, reduce distributive justice to an empirical question, it can merely provide the cardinal language in which we can ask about taxation and welfare.
Still, as I have argued above (), only (cardinal) utilitarianism can speak to the kind of aggregation that especially taxation and welfare require.
What we must do then, is to problematize --- not presume --- ideal observation, as @Rawls1988 has demanded.
In his *Theory of Justice*, @Rawls-1971, too, has suggested the mode for such observation that I choose here, and discuss further (p. ).
#### The Problem of Utility {#utility}
Question [\[itm:utility\]](#itm:utility){reference-type="ref" reference="itm:utility"} on utility is even thornier.
Behavioral economics, decision science and related disciplines present empirical findings that question whether humans have any *consistent* sense of utility, let alone a cardinal one.
This poses much harder questions for institutional design than the cognitive heuristics and biases, because from a utilitarian perspective there can be no such a thing as "flawed emotions".
Whatever people *feel* --- no matter how inconsistent --- are the last, and only consequences about which a utilitarian cares.
Certainly to a utilitarian, flawed *cognition* can and should be mitigated to improve its consequences, but there are no last reasons to correct human *emotion*, precisely because these *are* the last reason.
[^25]
I cannot here discuss at length the empirical findings on human emotion, but illustrate the questions it raises drawing only on some of @Kahneman2011's findings in prospect theory.
I suspect that related approaches will pose similar questions.
In his recent summary, [@Kahneman2011] poses at least two empirical critiques of [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-like human utility:
1. [\[itm:inconsistence\]]{#itm:inconsistence label="itm:inconsistence"}
Humans express their utility in inconsistent, non-[vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-preferences.
For example, people are not just *risk averse* --- as a convex utility function might explain ---, they are also *loss averse* [@KahnemanTversky1979].
From any given reference point, they seem to reap more hedonic gain from avoided *losses*, than from equally-sized missed *gains*.
As people make choices, their reference points can shift, and with that, their preference over the original choice can even *reverse*:
[@KahnemanTversky1979] find that when people have acquired mugs, they often accept only selling prices *higher* than their buying prices.
All of this spells trouble for [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-consistent preferences, and especially cardinal utility --- or willingness to pay --- on which orthodox economics relies:
prospect theory "is in many ways the least satisfactory of those considered since it allows individual choice to depend upon the context in which the choices were made" [@Grether1979 634].
Such deviations from consistent utility may also affect judgments of fairness in real life labor markets, as @Kahneman2011 [L5248] notes.
If confirmed, these findings may become relevant to macroeconomic policy and hypotheticals in welfare and taxation, too.
If, for example, a wage cut by any given amount causes more hedonic loss than a raise by the same, or even a higher amount creates hedonic gain, *creative destruction* [@SchumpeterSwedberg-1942-aa] may not be a utility optimum, even if it nominally were a positive-sum gain.
[^26]
Instead, from a utilitarian perspective, a general bias to conservatism may be warranted.
Similarly, taxation might have to be revamped to account for loss aversion.
Speculatively, if people suffered inordinate hedonic losses when parting with market earnings, taxation might have to be *less* progressive than otherwise desirable.
We might also have to *time* taxation so that it minimizes the *apparent* if not the real sense of loss.
For instance, withholding taxes at the source rather than a comprehensive [pit]{acronym-label="pit" acronym-form="singular+short"}, or generally indirect rather than direct taxes may be loss-aversively utilitarian, even if they were conventionally inefficient.
Interestingly, then, the equity implications of loss aversion are unclear.
Clearly, however, the abstractions of orthodox economics, and with it, conventional desiderata for hypothetical tax and welfare, are incapable of adequately capturing prospect theory, or other non-[vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-utility.
2. [\[itm:undefined\]]{#itm:undefined label="itm:undefined"}
More generally --- or equivalently? --- people may not only be unable to express consistent preferences, but there may be no such thing as well-defined utility, or subjective well-being.
@Kahneman2011 [7056], for one, describes three different operationalizations of subjective well-being:
[^27]
1. [\[itm:experienced\]]{#itm:experienced label="itm:experienced"}
Experienced well-being, reported *as* hedonic states occur.
2. [\[itm:remembered\]]{#itm:remembered label="itm:remembered"}
Remembered well-being, reported *after* some interval of hedonic states.
3. Hypothetical well-being, reported as the hedonic gain or loss ascribed *to* some non-outcome.
[^28]
If there were *one* such thing as subjective well-being, these three operationalizations --- and especially [\[itm:experienced\]](#itm:experienced){reference-type="ref" reference="itm:experienced"} and [\[itm:remembered\]](#itm:remembered){reference-type="ref" reference="itm:remembered"}, falsifiable *within-subjects* --- should yield the *same* hedonometer.
Trivially, remembered well-being should simply be the time-integral of experienced well-being.
Alas, it is not, as people seem to ignore duration and instead remember some (peak-end) *average* [@Kahneman2011 K7056].
What then, do we --- and happiness researchers --- mean, when we talk about subjective well-being? Clearly, none of the operationalizations alone can be satisfactory (pun intended) [see @Kahneman2011 K7056], but together, they do not add up to any *one* concept:
they are just inconsistent.
Utilitarianism, and with it, orthodox economics and consequentialist hypotheticals in welfare, tax and democracy face another empirical dead-end.
#### The Emptiness of Utilitarianism {#emptiness}
These twofold empirical dead-ends of utilitarianism pose not merely academic conundrums, they raise very fundamental problems in welfare and taxation.
Orthodox economics --- especially the welfare kind --- and many of the concepts I take for granted here all revert back to an empirically untenable assumption of [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-consistent, subjective consequences.
To say that an economy grows is to say that the net subjective consequences of people are improving along their [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-preferences.
To say that an economy has a positive savings rate is to say people are foregoing part of their [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-preferences now, and store them in some material (a house) or immaterial (a patent) form that will be [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-preferable in the future.
To a utilitarian economist --- almost a pleonasm! --- there is no *objective* value, other than [vnm]{acronym-label="vnm" acronym-form="singular+short"}-ranked *subjective* preferences, handily reported as utility, or willingness to pay.
<!-- %note that it's NOT prices, correct this -- the net of the two is the consumer surplus! -->
[^29]
[^30]
There may then be no *no* uncontested, objectifiable basis to value human choices and activity, as orthodox economics and much of the following desiderata in welfare and taxation.
Even if we subscribe to utilitarianism, we may not be able to reduce desirability to an unambigous empirical question.
[^31]
Rather, it appears, asking about preferences, or other subjective consequences, always begs *more* questions [confer @Kahneman2011], including about the *kind* of preference consistency, or the *kind* of subjective satisfaction --- about all of which we must find some kind of agreement.
Empirically, then, desirability cannot be reduced to a measurement of *pre-social* preferences, because these preferences, along with all that we may deduce from them, are only socially defined.
Willy-nilly, first-order inquiries into the utility of some choice have a habit of turning into second-order questions on the social conditions under which said utility was defined, measured and expressed.
<!-- %redundant? -->
What then, are we to make of this emptiness of utilitarianism?
Should we just abandon it and go for other ethics, instead? Surely, some caution is warranted, and we should back up normative claims with other ethics, because if nothing else, utilitarianism runs into these empirical dead-ends.
[^32]
I maintain that no matter these contradictions, we should stick to (some) form of utilitarianism, because normatively as ontologically, the world demands of us risky choices, that to choose one alternative is to negate another, and that as individuals and as societies, we must be willing and able to meaningfully trade-off desired outcomes.
The only way to do this at a scale, and under risk is to compute, as best we can, expected utilities.
Welfare and taxation, especially, ontologically presume, as much as they seek to improve comparable and consistent self-reported consequences.
If we are to make meaningful normative choices between factual and hypothetical welfare and tax, we must have a notion of utility.
But --- is that not cheating?
<!-- %maybe this should go into the later section -->
After all, I am justifying hypothetical taxation, welfare and democracy with last reasons that I know to be unconvincing, but posit them anyway because without them, I cannot justify hypothetical (or any!) taxation, welfare and democracy.
Admittedly, I *am* cheating, but I like to call it ethical pragmatism, instead.
I accept that in utilitarianism, as elsewhere, our moral judgements may be imperfect and tentative, but, to progress to greater clarity, must rely on them anyway, for three reasons:
1. Pragmatically, we must rely --- in part --- on utilitarian ethics because, for now, we are ontologically as empirically faced with a world that --- in part --- works according to it.
If you want to get something (deontologically?) good done today, you will probably have to appeal to popular notions of utility, no matter how ill-conceived they might be as last reasons.
2. Pragmatically, it is a safe bet that whatever we will deem good in the future, will, among other things, probably require not only negative entropy, but more specifically, *stuff* that people prefer, including shelter, food and clothing.
Of course, we may be less certain about many other things that people ostensibly now prefer --- luxury cars, computers carved out of solid aluminum, espresso machines --- and end up producing (future) "utility", that does not hold up on (future) ethical reflection.
Still, we should better be safe with *some* attractive subjective consequences, rather than sorry without *any* such utility.
<!-- %this should report stuff that people "roughly vnM-report" -->
3. Lastly, and also pragmatically, we can further --- but not perfect --- our ethical understanding of subjective consequences by problematizing, then improving those very social conditions under which we empirically seem to be forming our preferences.
<!-- %notably, the whole social influence literature is still missing in here.
%Might have to add that up top later.
%Actually, maybe that's ok, because I am dealing with a normative theory here, and merely test whether it's empirically possible.
%The social influence stuff might rather go into the ontology section.
%!!! this is very important; both deliberation and taxation (PCT!) are actually institutions to improve this problem of isolation under utilitiaranism:
%it may help us to intersubjectively compare value, as well as to become clearer about what it means to ourselves.
%!here is a crazy idea:
%maybe "erfahrungen auf vorrat" -- popular culture -- is in fact this; it's trying for us to get some better idea of how we might like different things, before, during and after the fact. -->
If utility is, in fact, *not* pre-socially given, we can meaningfully *talk* about it.
Of course, *that* is cheating, too.
By problematizing the social conditions of forming preferences, I have just reassigned a first-order question (utility) to second-order status, a move I otherwise despise.
To do this in a normative ethic, is really just to rephrase the question:
after all, to *what*, if not a utilitarian standard, do you hold the social condition of preference-formation?
I allow myself this trick not because it resolves the confusion, but simply to organize my discussion of welfare, tax and democracy.
Welfare and taxation, are --- by definition --- the realms in which the social conditions of preference formation are *not* problematized.
Here, I ontologically assume, and normatively require preferences to be (largely) pre-social.
Democracy, in turn, is *the* social condition under which we form preferences in intersubjective deliberation.
[^33]
Here, I ontologically assume, and normatively require preferences to be (largely) social.
### Justice as Fairness {#fair}
Desirable hypotheticals in welfare, tax and democracy are just if they treat people fairly.
Justice --- especially *distributive* justice --- deals with *men in the plural* as @Arendt1958 demanded of political theory, and regulates competing claims between people.
As we have seen, some of the previous ethics tell us little about how to resolve conflicts *between* different bearers of rights, virtue, consequences or care, respectively.
Deontological liberalism provides some digital rules, but these tend to be either minimal, or overly restrictive.
Consequentialist utilitarianism promised to make aggregation an empirical matter, but cannot do so convincingly.
Crucially, neither of these ethics suggests how conflicts over the meaning of, or conflicts between competing claims can be resolved.
Here again, I turn to John @Rawls-1971 to provide a meta-standard for finding desirable hypotheticals.
In his influential "Theory of Justice", he provides that standard:
*justice as fairness*.
Ever the liberal [and similar to above-mentioned @Cohen-1989-aa], he suggests *no* definite desiderata, but instead proposes a thought experiment under which moral claims have to qualify to be admissible for consideration.
In his thought experiment, @Rawls-1971 imagines an *original position*, where deliberators know nothing about their endowments, status and power in the real world.
Only moral claims that can be defended under such a *veil of ignorance*, suggests @Rawls-1971, may --- but need not be --- just.
Oddly, this imagined original position is *almost* a liberal procedure for justice, or a normative claim of the *second* order --- but not quite.
The veil of ignorance, is, of course, materially impossible and operates only metaphorically.
Justice as fairness, is, instead, an *end-state theory of (distributive) justice* [@Fried1999 1007].
Genially, Rawls has thereby crafted a standard of *substantive* justice, avoiding both the contingency of immediate imperatives ("\[shellfish\] shall be an abomination to you", Leviticus 11: 8, KJV), the nihilism
[^34]
under procedural prescriptions ("Law to Rectify the Destitution of the People and the Empire", Berlin 1933) and the vagueness of substantive universalisms ("life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness", US Declaration of Independence 1776).
If ever there can be a synthesis between natural and positive law, it must be similar to Rawls.
<!-- %\citep[90]{GutmannThompson-2004-aa}:
%``This kind of public philosophy would avoid the dichotomy that has come to dominate contemporary discussions of political theory, which poses a choice between basing politics on a comprehensive conception of the good, on the one hand, or limiting politics to a conception of procedural justice, on the other.
%We can and should avoid choosing either of these approaches exclusively.'' -->
@Rawls-1971' Theory of Justice suits me, because as a liberal proposal, it lets me "economize on moral disagreement" [@GutmannThompson-2004-aa K226].
Moreover, both Rawls' original position and the distributive justice he deduces from it, align neatly with deliberative democracy and progressive taxation of (postpaid) consumption, as I argue in (p. ).
<!-- %hehe, so you're choosing a standard that you know will work well? That's a not playing fair.
%or maybe, include the difference principle here already if it works for both deliberation AND PCT? and what about the LVT?
%add to this:
%pragmatic section on virtue ethics?
%add to this:
%pragmatic section on ethics of care? -->
<!-- provisionally accept homo oec + abstractions -->
### Meta trade-offs
These are the axioms for desirable hypotheticals in tax, welfare and democracy.
I hope they will garner wide-spread support.
Admittedly, the aforementioned axioms are woefully unspecific to design the institutions of tax, welfare and democracy.
For the time being, they must remain so.
I develop them into domain-specific desiderata in later chapters.
The aforementioned axioms have also not resolved all conflicts between initial, tentative desiderata nor have they resolved the contradictions between different ethics.
I suggest two modes of resolving such conflicts.
1. In part, I resolve these conflicts *by hierarchy*.
Following @Rawls-1971, desirable hypotheticals must be liberal and must maintain the most extensive basic liberties compatible with similar liberty for others.
Such norms --- as is typical for deontological ethics --- are *categorical*:
these liberties are either given, or not.
Such categorical values may also conflict, as for example, freedom of speech and human dignity may, in cases of alleged defamation.
In these cases, desirable hypotheticals are those arrangements that satisfy *both* freedom of speech and human dignity until and unless they conflict.
Crucially, neither norm is superior and they cannot be continuously traded off one another:
there is no *amount* of cardinally "more" free speech that would justify a cardinal loss in human dignity.
Categorical values defy trade-offs.
What we must look for, instead, are *intersecting sets* in a figurative Euler diagram, as in (p. ).
\centering
![Euler Diagram of Three Values[]{label="fig:euler-values"}](euler-values){#fig:euler-values width="100%"}
All remaining values must be reconciled within this intersect of categorical values of liberalism.
Here too, even supposedly outsized cardinal gains in any of the remaining values cannot be traded off nominal violations of categorical values.
2. In part, I resolve these conflicts by offering trade-offs.
This works only for values that are continuous in their realization, as may be the case for the tired conflict between equity and efficiency in taxation.
I suggest that the trade-offs offered by such conflicting, continuous values depend crucially on the institutional context under which these trade-offs have to be engaged.
Calling trade-offs, and designing the conditions thereof can be illustrated well in a diagram of [ppfs]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="plural+short"}, frequently used in economics to illustrate different possible baskets of goods that can be produced by an economy.
Because paper as this is two-dimensional, [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} diagrams frequently only show two goods, but the abstraction carries to any number of $n$ goods in a basket.
I adapt the traditional [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} in (p. ).
\centering
![Production-Possibility Frontiers of Two Competing Values[]{label="fig:ppf-values"}](ppf-values){#fig:ppf-values width="100%"}
What are competing goods in a [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} diagram are here competing values $I$ and $II$.
Let us assume for the sake of simplicity that these values can be easily measured and are ratio scaled.
More of each value is better.
The four [ppfs]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="plural+short"} are comprised of those possible combinations of values $I$ and $II$ which are *furthest* from the origin, and thereby strictly preferable over all possible policies *under* the [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"}.
As in a static model of the economy, the [ppfs]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="plural+short"} are exogenously determined by a priori, and posteriori limits of the first order.
In addition, I argue, these exogenous limits are modified by *institutions* $1$ through $4$.
Policies $A$ through $J$ are defined by specific combinations of continuous value $1$ and $2$, along the respective institutions which modify what is logically and empirically possible in this world.
illustrates different policy choices.
The simplest kind of trade-off is that between two policies along a linear [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"}, as between $A$ and $B$ on $1$.
A straight [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} implies that the values are substituted at a constant rate:
any increase in $I$ will requires a decrease in $II$ by the same amount.
The choice between $A$ and $B$, as all other points on $1$ is a zero-sum proposition.
As we shall see, trade-offs in welfare, taxation and democracy are frequently, if implicitly, presented as such zero-sum choices.
Alternatives of this sort are inevitable, but they are also normatively less interesting.
Once values $I$ and $II$ are reduced to the same scale, the choice along the resultant [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} becomes trivial or even arbitrary.
[^35]
<!-- %add refs to later misunderstandings here -->
[ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} $4$ is curvilinear, and more interesting.
Here, the rate of substitution varies over different levels of $I$ or $II$.
For example, around $G$, you have to give up relatively little in $I$ to gain relatively much in $II$.
The reverse is true around $H$, and substitution is roughly constant around $J$.
The trade-offs between $I$ and $II$ are non-zero-sum:
you can gain more than you loose.
Assuming a reasonable aggregate indifference curve (linear or convex), optimal policy will probably lie around $J$.
As we shall see, concave or other curvilinear [ppfs]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="plural+short"} abound in welfare, tax and democracy.
Recognizing the convexity of trade-offs offered by any given institution, or, if possible, moving from lower, linear [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} $1$ to a higher, convex [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} $4$ will be important to identify desirable hypotheticals.
[ppfs]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="plural+short"} $1$ and $3$ are both linear, but they have different slopes.
At any level of $I$, compared to [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} $1$ you have to sacrifice more in $I$ to increase $II$.
The moves *along* curve $3$ are otherwise as normatively uninteresting as those along [ppf]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="singular+short"} $1$ --- the two are just scaled differently --- but the choice *between* these two institutions will be very consequential.
Compared to institution $1$, institution $3$ will always make it costlier to increase value $II$.
There are many such consequential choices of institutions in tax, welfare and democracy.
[ppfs]{acronym-label="ppf" acronym-form="plural+short"} $1$ and $2$ both have the same slope, but $2$ is further from the origin.
By definition, all policies along this higher curve are preferable to all policies on the lower curve --- to everyone.
[^36]
This is the most important of institutional choices to be made.
<!-- %hehe, here's a pretty big part of the story missing:
%the DEMAND side.
%You'd need indifference curves!
%note how justice as fairness falls in-between these \ldots it's somewhere in-between all of those
%why is this pragmatic? -->
## The Ontology of the Doable Hypothetical {#ontology}
<!-- %ontology is the stuff that I am dealing with
%``(\ldots) every research agenda must start from some basic assumption about human nature, and the assumption of my research agenda is that despite all the evil in the world, at least some humans have, some of the time, a sense of goodness in truly caring for the well-being of others.'' \cite[7]{Steiner2012} -->
> But what is government itself, but the greatest of all reflections on human nature?
>
> --- James @Madison1788 [143]
Doable hypotheticals are preferable to others because, in @Dahl-1989-aa's words, "we must avoid comparing ideal oranges with actual apples" [-@Dahl-1989-aa 84].
Deciding just what can, and cannot be done is hard.
If asked as a positive first-order question, the answer is sometimes empirically unclear.
If turned into a second-order question --- as the social sciences are prone to do --- the answer becomes politically contested.
Both extremes do not serve us well:
1. When all inquiries into the social world are reduced to positive, first-order questions the social sciences effectively abolish themselves and make the status quo epistemologically endogenous, as in:
*social inequality is inevitable human nature, because if it were not, it would not be observed*, or "the Laws of commerce are the laws of Nature, and therefore the laws of God." (@Burke1790 as cited in @Marx-1867-aa [834]).
2. Conversely, when such inquiries assign all positive questions to second-order status, the social sciences hermetically seal themselves off from other disciplines and turn critique into futile, infinite regress, as in:
*"social being \[...\] determines \[...\] consciousness"* [@Marx1859 Preface], including, one might add, Marxist consciousness.
<!-- %find out that one piece that argues that social scientists are leftist because they get paid by the state -->
Instead, the social sciences --- and especially policy analysis --- should find a middle ground, taking on *one second-order question at a time*, while provisionally leaving all other questions to first-order status.
I here ask second-order questions about the welfare state, taxation and democracy and I therefore assume these *institutions* to be malleable.
*Not* under study here are (p. ) or the (p. ), especially of developed states and late capitalist economic production.
I assume these to be constant in the medium run and reasonably approximated in the following sections.
### Human Nature {#human-nature}
Any second-order prescription for how to organize production, distribution and decision making rests on assumptions about human nature.
For evolutionary anthropology, psychology, behavioral economics and other offspring of now disreputable [@Wright1994] sociobiology [@Wilson1975] this is a positive first-order question about our prehistoric baggage:
what behavioral, cognitive and emotional dispositions might have been adaptive in the environment of our evolution, and what do we observe today?
#### Evolution and Morality
Maybe, evolution deserves to be the master ontology of life, and therefore, of human life, too.
Because I sometimes refer to such Neo-Darwinian arguments [@Wright1994] and hear them often misunderstood I must reiterate the ontological status of the theory of evolution:
1. Evolution may dispose us to think, feel and act in certain ways, but does not determine us to do so (*deterministic fallacy*).
2. Evolution yields more ("gradual" according to Neo-Darwinism) or less ("punctuated" according @Elrdredge1972) stable *equilibria* between environmental conditions and (more or less) adaptive traits of organisms.
It does not necessarily yield *optimal* configurations, just survival of the relatively fitt*er*.
Conversely, not all biological features that are observed are necessarily adaptive, but may simply be side consequences of other, adaptive features or developmental vestiges [@Gould].
Or, in @Bryson2003's succinct formulation, "life wants to be, but it doesn't want to be much" [@Bryson2003].
3. [\[itm:nonmoral\]]{#itm:nonmoral label="itm:nonmoral"}
Evolution is a "nonmoral" process [@Gould1982].
It may tend towards greater complexity and cooperation, including human-like intelligence [@Wright2000], or it may just pursue a random walk, departing from a "left wall" [@Gould1994 4] of "simple beginnings" [@Gould1977 7], and inevitably bring some complexity, including *homo sapiens* as a freak outlier [@Gould1996].
Either way, even if evolution *were* directional, it would not be along any moral dimension intelligible to humans.
This cuts both ways:
1. to praise evolutionary results is to fall for a *"naturalistic fallacy"* (@Moore1903, as cited in @Wright2000 [K5987])